THE LIMITATIONS OF BLACK NATIONALISM: GARVEYISM AND THE INDEPENDENCE MOVEMENT IN THE WEST INDIAN DIASPORA Renaldo C. McKenzie
THE LIMITATIONS OF BLACK NATIONALISM: GARVEYISM
AND THE INDEPENDENCE MOVEMENT IN THE WEST INDIAN DIASPORA
Renaldo C. McKenzie
West Indian and Caribbean nationalists, including Garveyites, contributed to the anti-imperialist and decolonization movements and struggles. However, West Indian nationalists broadly did not question capitalism and the class relations of exploitation on which it has rested. In the end, the nationalist movement left the struggle for independence with major deficits, including those nationalist narratives that sought to produce “national literatures based on working class and peasant culture” (Rosenberg 1). When nationalists speak in the name of the working class, they leave the impression of espousing a working class political agenda. However, their project does not break with bourgeois consciousness and they never manage to see a way beyond capitalism. They may imagine ways to reduce foreign penetration, domination and what passes for ‘cultural imperialism,’ however this stance reinforces capitalist class relations and bourgeois ideology while it fails to benefit the working class in any fundamental way.
The Black Nationalists and the Independent Movements earlier leaders such as Garvey Muhammad et al embarked on a “myth-making” mission in attempt to lift themselves up from the ashes of society. However, the mistake they made is to align themselves with white-identity to achieve freedom. But this is not a bad criticism, as this was a necessary step in the process of achieving universal freedom for all humanity. To limit the fright to its racial ethnicities and components is to give power to those who “divide and conquer”, But Black people needed to feel good about themselves first before they universalize the struggle. These are some of the issues we must engage to arrive at whether black nationalism is relevant or even limited in its ability to realize its goals.
Leah Rosenberg says exile helped to shape the “joint emergence of Caribbean nationalism and literature” (4) within an anti-imperialist context that gave rise to a cultural nationalist consciousness that left a strong and often damaging imprint on the character of the working class and labor struggles around decolonization and independence. There is no doubt that among the nationalists, Garveyites did much to awaken the ideological and political consciousness of masses of West Indians at home and in the African Diaspora. Frank Furedi has shown, in The Silent War: Imperialism and the Silent Discourse of Race (1998), that British and American diplomats in the West Indies and in Africa were very concerned about what they reported on as a high degree of race consciousness among Caribbean blacks with respect to the meaning and implications of Italy’s invasion of Ethiopia in 1936, as well as about the racialized class domination and exploitation and racist oppression in the Caribbean.
Garveyism therefore contributed to the development of anti-colonialism, anti-imperialism and anti-racism among ‘African Diaspora’ populations. However, it is necessary to make distinctions between Garveyism as articulated by Marcus Garvey, especially his emphasis on the racial nationalist and the ‘Fascist’ basis of his ideology and political aspirations, and the ways Diaspora blacks appropriated his ideas and applied them to their concrete situations in the anti-colonial and anti-imperialist struggles. In fact, the political significance of Garvey’s contribution transcended his way of trying to invert white supremacy to promote a form of racial black supremacy around his notion of ‘Africa for Africans.’ Garvey gave the mistaken impression that there was or could be a racial essence to blackness that transcended the horrible experience of enslavement, racial and gender oppression, the racialization of class differences and the horrors of colonialism and imperialism.
Rosenberg’s observations on the pitfalls of nationalist consciousness in the Caribbean are equally applicable to the contributions by labor leaders and political and cultural nationalists. George Lamming has been one of the most astute observers and critics of West Indian political and cultural nationalism. Lamming understands race as a social construction but he shares with nationalists certain romantic conceptions about the nation that have conditioned how he looks at decolonization, self-determination and independence. Lamming contributes to an impression that the crafters of the independence movements did not get nationalism right, a perspective that seems to target the symptoms of the problem rather than the substantive problems with nationalism which bring us back to epistemological questions about the nature of nations and culture (see Clarke passim). These are issues that sooner or later turn on methodological and theoretical questions about the nature of history, human nature, culture and matters of space and time. When we make the state of nature our starting
point for theorizing about history we invariably end up historicizing and objectifying nature and naturalizing history, culture and time-space with the effect of immobilizing theory by superimposing on it a teleological interpretation of events (see Jahn).
In the arguments I discuss below, I address issues surrounding Garveyism and Black Nationalism as a consequence of the racialization of power and class relations. I explore Black Nationalism and the Independence Movement and tracing significant events in their history that shows the enormity of the task to succeed against the system, and the limitations of the movements. I treat the concept of race as a social construct, rather than a matter of phenotype (see Mills). I discuss the conceptual and logical problem with using something which does not exist — biological race — as the starting point for proving its existence which pertains to raciology and raciological thinking within Garveyism as a sub sector of Black Nationalism (see Watson). I will argue that mainstream or ‘moderate Enlightenment’ discourses, which were associated with certain major thinkers such as Locke, Hume, Rousseau, Voltaire, Kant, Montesquieu, Turgot, and Smith, among others, tended toward a monist conception of universal humanity (see Israel, Kedourie, et al); however, those individuals contradicted themselves by attributing the causes of inequality to racial differences (see Malik). In effect, the moderate (mainstream) Enlightenment contributed to the racialization of history and helped to lay the foundations of the ideological and political domination that has been used to justify racialization and global white supremacy, which catalyzed an accidental version of Black Nationalism and “Power” within the diaspora.
I identify a contrasting ‘radical Enlightenment’ which insisted on the equal worth of all humans without respect to differences in culture, geography, language, ethnicity, or level of material development and social consciousness. Theorists of the ‘radical Enlightenment’ adopted an anti-colonial and anti-imperialist perspective and insisted that Europe did not have a monopoly on progressive ideas (see Israel). In The Theft of History (2006), Jack Goody condemns the teleological reasoning that locates Europe at the center of the universe and insists that the habit of tracing European progress to the ancient Greeks and Romans, while denying the contributions of other societies, contradicts reliable historical evidence. I argue that naturalistic materialism impeded the development of theoretical consciousness and knowledge partly by superimposing religious ideas on reason and science, a tendency that was evident among a range of Enlightenment thinkers like Locke and Turgot (see Israel).蜉 Philosophy is about what is, what ought to be, that which is normative. However, My paper will not only explore the philosophical underpinnings of the black idea of nationalism, but also the anthropological considerations, what follows from that within a current and practical social issue of Race and the limitations of Garveyism as a foundational black nationalist movement and philosophical school of thought. Where is the movement, How is the nationalism perceived through people’s interpretations of the events.
Naturalistic Materialism and Idealism: Their Influence on Marcus Garvey and Garveyism
Naturalistic materialism derives both ideas and social factors from the purely “physical properties” (van der Pijl 131) and idealism derives all reality from “purely mental forces (spirit)” (131) and separates contemplative intellectual functions from any shared social experience. Naturalistic materialism and idealism, which conditioned the ideas and beliefs of Marcus Garvey and Garveyism as a ‘black nationalist’ ideology and political movement, is reflected in Garvey’s way of superimposing a religious ideology (Christianity) on science and scientific interpretations of historical change. His ideas were Kantian, represented a European version of nationalism and self-determinism necessitated by reason. Garvey was well versed in critical and intellectual thinking. He believed, like Kant, in a universal society, a unity of Africans everywhere to make his black nation with their own constitutional rights work. Contextually, Garvey’s ideas worked against the integration of manual and mental labor, with the effect of undermining the growth of theoretical consciousness, given its anti-materialist, anti-humanist, and its decidedly romanticist and heavily racial-nationalist and Christian outlook.
Wilmot Blyden asserted that black Africa was plagued by ‘tribal paganism’ and he advocated a role for Christianity and Islam to purge Africa of its tribal pagan traditions to bring its people into the modern world. Influenced by Descartes and Kant and Plato, Blyden’s interpretation of African history rested on a dualist conception that anticipated the coming of Western modernization theory with its linear conception of change. Realistically, the internationalization of social life helps to undermine national one-sidedness and narrow-mindedness and helps a society to develop and strengthen its “creative capacity to shape its own destiny” (van der Pijl 129) as part of the larger struggle for our universal humanity. Kees van der Pijl argues that the tendency toward the transformation of “contemplative philosophy” into “experimental natural science” (130) was at an early point in its development when the Enlightenment was taking shape. He contends that the moment was not marked by the convergence of physical labour and practical philosophy and anthropology in science and industry, and it was in this specific context that naturalistic materialism arose within social and political thought with the effect of idealizing ‘purely mental forces (spirit)’ and rupturing the integral relationship of contemplative intellectual functions with shared social experience. In order to achieve the “social synthesis” (130) of manual and mental labour, there has to be a deepening of social relations at the international level along lines of scientific, technological and cultural change which requires breaking down the arbitrary separation between forms of national and international life (130). Racial nationalist interpretations of history of the sort that typify white supremacy and Garveyism obstruct progress toward the integration of national and international life.
The environment necessary for ‘social synthesis’ to occur requires a social setting with material and subjective conditions of a high level of material culture. Naturalistic materialism could not foster such conditions because it rested on a “dualistic opposition” between mental and manual labor that obstructs the realization of a “mutual dependence” between “knowledge and labour.” Under naturalistic materialism, science is subject to the sway of religion which is conducive to the objective idealism that typified the outlook of the ‘moderate’ Enlightenment and Romanticist tendency from
Locke, Turgot, Voltaire, and Kant to G. W. F. Hegel and Max Weber (van der Pijl 131- 132; see also Israel). Locke, Turgot, Kant and Hegel embraced naturalistic materialism as expressed in the metaphysical notion of “God and the soul” existing independently of “scientific inquiry” and human material and social existence. The emergence of agnosticism did not only stifle the development of materialism, it also introduced a false dichotomy between politics and religion and between science and religion (van der Pijl 134).
Naturalistic materialism has also influenced the interpretation of race and the development of raciological thinking of the sort that racial (cultural) nationalists privilege. Ashley Montagu argues that race “is itself a racist term not simply because it represents a congeries of errors . . . but . . . most importantly, because it’s baleful influence constitutes a threat to the very existence of humanity” (47). Richard Lewontin argues
That human racial classification is of no social value and is positively destructive of social and human relations. Since such racial classification is . . . of virtually no genetic or taxonomic significance either, no justification can be offered for its continuance. (396-97)
Paul Gilroy writes that
there is something worthwhile to be gained from a deliberate renunciation of ‘race’ as the basis for belonging to one another and acting in concert. . . . The idea that action against racial hierarchies can proceed effectively when it has been purged of any lingering respect for the idea of ‘race’ is one of the most persuasive cards in this political and ethical suit. (12).
Kenan Malik points out that “equality is not an ‘inalienable’ right” (39) but a social right that is created “through human endeavour” (39) which highlight the “social nature of equality and the dilemmas this often creates” (39) and underscore “the ambiguous attitude of Western society towards the notion of race” (39). Malik insists that it is not “racial differentiation that has led to the denial of equality, but the social constraints placed on the scope of equality that has led to the racial categorization of humanity” (39). It is “inequality that gives rise to ‘race’” (39) and racial classification in modern class society. The racialization of states and their societies and the institutionalization of racial nationalism and ‘racial rule’ by and through the modern state, mask the actual class basis of economic inequality and oppression (see Goldberg). The problem posed around the monist interpretation of history that Enlightenment thought advanced is that it failed to overcome naturalistic materialism and idealism both of which subordinate science and material process to religious ideology and other teleological accounts of history. This problem came to light in the Enlightenment scientific (monist) idea that race and racial difference (understood in biological and raciological terms) were the causes of inequality in the world.
Marcus Garvey and Garveyism drew on ideological currents that had already germinated in Europe, the United States, and the colonial world. There is evidence of strong Eurocentric ideological currents within Garveyism. It is this fact that draws our attention to the international cultural context that shaped both International Relations (IR) as area of academic inquiry (see Jahn 2000: xi-xvi) and Garveyism as a political and ideological movement for the mobilization, politicization, and redemption of Africans and people of African descent. Garvey’s assertion that his was the first fascist movement is indicative of the European roots of his ideological orientation. Garveyism bears the hallmarks of what Paul Gilroy calls ‘transatlantic modernity.’
Garvey viewed capitalism as the proper model of development for Africa and the African Diaspora. He saw capitalism foremost as a modernizing force for the uplift of Africa and the people of African descent around the world. The problem with this particular conception of progress is that Garvey imposed a raciological conception of history on economic change, thus subordinating the rationalist and scientific process of capitalist expansion and development to teleological (raciological) forces. Like earlier leading English thinkers who sojourned in the British West Indies (BWI) and/or wrote about the interests and property rights of British capitalists under African enslavement — Bryan
Edwards, Edward Long, and James Anthony Froude (see Froude; see also Benn) — Garvey also drew heavily on teleological arguments to develop his perspective. The response by J. J. Thomas of Trinidad to the writings of Froude about Africans and their descendants in the New World differed by degree rather than kind from what English and European thinkers asserted.
Wilmot Blyden asserted that Africa was plagued by ‘tribal paganism’ and he called on European Christianity and Islam to extirpate it. Blyden implied that African cultures were static and unchanging and needed external intervention to liberate them from what he saw as their natural backwardness. Blyden read African history in a linear fashion. He saw Africans as an anachronism and he banished them from the time and space to which they belonged, much the way the Europeans imagined the Amerindians a few centuries before (see Jahn). In Blyden’s estimation, the cultural practices of Africans had to be destroyed to transform them into modern subjects in order to live under the civil law of capitalism and bourgeois property relations based on the political economy of labor time.
Substantively, Blyden’s ‘tribal paganism’ is a cultural invention for the expansion of a particular civilization. He contributes to the dualistic conception of the world and presages European modernization theory with its idea of backward non-European cultures juxtaposed against modern and naturally progressive European cultures. Like certain nineteenth century black American thinkers such as Martin Delaney, Blyden also imagined ‘Africa for Africans’ and Europe for Europeans, a raciological mode of reasoning that appealed to Garvey. Jack Goody argues against such a linear account of historical change by insisting that only through processes of complex interactions has cultural progress been achieved in the world. There is a fundamental difference between Blyden’s ideas and Jack Goody’s — Goody sees something useful in all cultures while Blyden emphasized negative forces in African cultures.
Garvey’s Assertion of the Fascist Roots of his Ideology
Garvey wanted to rearrange the chairs on the deck of the ship of liberal imperialism rather than to abolish imperialism. He was not an anti-imperialist and his credentials as black racial nationalist separates him from emancipatory strategies that could liberate blacks from oppression and economic exploitation. Garvey insisted that those who fought against capitalism were "enemies of human advancement" (see Padmore 83-84), sensing that capitalism was the driving force behind the juggernaut of imperialism and the dominant nation-states in the West which he imagined that he could emulate (see Persaud). Like the Nazis, Garvey also eschewed socialism and communism and he extolled the virtues of capitalism within a narrow racial communitarian context. He appealed to the Ku Klux Klan to help him secure black American autonomy in exchange for his support for the Ku Klux Klan to control whites as a pure race to maintain the imputed purity of the white race.
George Padmore argued that Garveyism was an obstacle to the "mass Negro struggle for liberation against American imperialism" (xv). Padmore sought to separate Pan Africanism from Garveyism, arguing that Pan-Africanism "identifies itself with the neutral camp, opposed . . . all forms of oppression and racial chauvinism – white and black – and associates itself with all forces of progress and goodwill, regardless of nationality, race, color, or creed, working for universal brotherhood, social justice, and peace for all peoples everywhere" (xvi). Padmore insisted that Pan-Africanism embraced "much that is true in the Marxist interpretation of history" (xvi), while rejecting the intolerance of doctrinaire Communism. He asserted that a “society in which all men are equal regardless of their color or race is to most Europeans utopian" (320). Even after Padmore broke with Moscow, he did not embrace the outlook Garvey held toward socialism and communism which Garvey rejected as ungodly.
Neither Garvey nor his defenders have managed to tell us how his ‘back to Africa’ notion could be translated into practical activity, how many of the new diaspora ethnic groups who had been forged on the workbench of capitalism under enslavement and post emancipation would be willing to return to places they did not know and that were linguistically and culturally alien to them.
For Blyden, the Africans would have to subject their desire, which had been shaped fundamentally by the requirements of subsistence production, to the wage labor imperatives of the capitalist production process, as part of the price for becoming modern. Blyden imagined that such a transformation was essential for dispensing with the tribal paganism he attributed to sub-Saharan Africans. Of course, many Africans had been integrated with modern production under imperialism in conditions where their labor power was still much cheaper than technology, hence the extended day and brutal working conditions that were the norm.
What Garvey thought could be cured through wage labor; Blyden had already imagined being an inherent property of the existence of the African. Garvey relied on a teleological interpretation of capitalism which he equated with an inherent drive in human nature, a view that reflected his pessimistic view of history, the nature of the world, culture and change. All things including race and racial conflict seemed predetermined by God, a belief that removes human agency from the equation of change. One would be hard pressed to argue that Garvey offered a scientific theory of history and human progress.
Garvey, War and Imperialism
It is well known that Garvey admired the European ruling classes for the steely determination with which they expanded their empires and he saw them as his role models. In fact, he imagined that the motion of history was determined by the conflict and struggles among the races (see Watson). This point perhaps more than any other necessitates addressing the question of war in relation to Garveyism. There was no reliable evidence that Africans and diaspora “negroes” sought revenge through war and violence against their enslavers and imperialist oppressors, along racial or racist lines (see Furedi in this regard). The rebellions and other forms of insurgency that slaves organized and executed in the Caribbean were fundamentally about asserting their humanity and freeing themselves from the multiple forms of oppression and dehumanization to which they were subjugated. In asserting their humanity through their acts of rebellion they were also implying that it was possible to liberate their oppressors. It was not clear however that, as the St. Domingue Revolution demonstrated through its specific unfolding, the aim was to end the exploitation of man by man. Whether the Haitian Revolution was capable of becoming a complete (social) revolution in the geopolitical context of its own articulation raises larger theoretical and empirical questions.
Gilroy argues that whatever problems we might encounter in categorizing the Ku Klux Klan as fascist, it is necessary to keep in mind the issue that “justifies an association between an openly Nazi organization and a spiritual movement dedicated to the emancipation, uplift, and protection of Africans abroad. It is . . . the acquisition of sovereign territory, a national homeland, a piece of ground, which legitimates these aspirations” (236) that remains an enduring force in the formation of national subjectivity. In 1974, Marcus Garvey, Jr., one of Garvey’s sons, said that
African National Socialism postulates that the children of the Black God of Africa have a date with destiny. We shall recreate the glories of ancient Egypt, Ethiopia and Nubia. It is natural that the children of mother Africa scattered in the great diaspora will cleave together once more. It seems certain that the world will one day be faced with the black cry of an African ‘Anschluss’ and the resolute demand for African ‘lebensraum’” (Garvey, Jr. 387; also qtd. in Gilroy, 236).
Clearly, Marcus Garvey Jr. ideas had not matured beyond the ideological consciousness of his father. The notion of an African ‘Lebensraum’ implied fighting old battles of imperialism in an age where classical imperialism had already given way to an emerging transnational capitalist hegemony.
Could blacks in Africa and in the African Diaspora benefit from the promotion of an emancipation struggle waged on fascist criteria (see Black; see also Kuhl)? What technologies of war might Garvey’s mother Africa employ to execute its ‘lebensraum’ project, and at what point do we confront the reality that war can be employed as an instrument against the particular state Marcus Garvey Jr. had in mind (see Reid)? What form of internationalism might Garvey have mounted to sustain international solidarity and internationalism among Africans and ‘Diaspora Negroes’ within an imperialist, antisocialist context, considering that internationalism was a decidedly socialist and communist project that he eschewed?
Unyielding racial nationalism had driven Nazism to its extreme practices of brutalism, masculinism and violence in war and genocide. Broadly-speaking, Garvey’s values resonated with conservative Christian precepts and anti-humanist individualism. He said:
In our desire to achieve greatness as a race, we are liberal enough to extend to others a similar right. . . . All races should be pure in morals and in outlook, and for that we, as Negroes, admire the leaders and members of the Anglo-Saxon clubs. They are honest and honorable in their desire to purify and standardize our race. (338)
Garvey compared his strategy with the white supremacist project which amounted to inverting white supremacy to suit his designs. The implication was that under different circumstances white supremacy could become black supremacy. Yet, as Charles Mills argues, the question does not turn on phenotype but on power relations (127). Garvey found it difficult to think of power outside of racial terms. He wanted a racial order that would suit his aims, which meant reducing race to a pure biological category in the same way that Adolf Hitler sought to dehistoricize the concept of race in order to create a new ‘anti-historic order.’ Hitler wrote in a letter to Hermann Rauschning that
I know perfectly well just as all those tremendously clever intellectuals that in the scientific sense there is no such thing as race. . . . I as politician need a conception which enables the order which has hitherto existed on historic bases to be abolished and an entirely new and anti-historic order enforced and given intellectual basis. . . . With the conception of race, National Socialism will carry its revolution abroad and recast the world (Qtd. in Montagu, 81).
From the two passages quoted above, it is clear that Hitler and Garvey acknowledged that the historical conception of race did not suit their purposes. The racialization of global politics with a view to the creation of a new hierarchical (racial) international order was central to Hitler’s project. Hitler acquired the state power and force to execute his fascist project to create the impossible — an Aryan race. Garvey thanked white supremacists for helping to purify that which did not exist in the world — a biological African race — with the aim of making blacks come to terms with the imperative nature of their emancipation. Garvey’s assertion of the fascist basis of his project did not offer a viable means toward the liberation of those in whose names he claimed to speak from the “repertory of power that produced their sufferings in the first place” (Gilroy 14, 6). A world viewed in terms of struggles among races is a world destined to reproduce itself through the medium of violence, force and war.
What we need is a critique of the
strategy of power that informs the development of social relations under the duress of the modern state. . . . The counter-strategic tradition exposes the ways in which this conception of war as a dialectical form only serves to reproduce the methods by which the state governs the force of war, bringing its movement within its control, and countermanding it to its own degenerative purposes (Reid 295).
In the Prussian tradition, Karl von Clausewitz viewed war as a “conflict of living forces” (85; also qtd. in Reid, 279), a “form of commerce and international transactions and as the continuation of policy with other means” (85; also qtd. in Reid, 279). Garvey’s concern with war connects with his interest in commerce, though he did not develop any successful commercial ventures within the highly competitive environment of capitalist imperialism. He implied that race and, by extension, the notion of a collective black consciousness constituted a fixed identity that served as the absolute structuring principle in interstate relations.
Garvey’s ideas do not tell us how it is possible to protect societies from the state and war in spite of the fact that, dialectically, war can be pursued as a force against the state — as a form of the “violence of a movement that breaks from the distribution and strategization of forces that compose existing social relations” (Reid 287, 288, 294).
Individuals like Garvey, whether they are European or other, who rejects the radical Enlightenment in order to embrace nationalist western or non-western philosophical thought, must account for where they stand on the “basic equality of all men, tactically endorsing the subordination and disadvantaging of long despised minorities . . . as well as of women” (Israel 869) and other victims.
Trajectory of Black Struggle in the Americas and the Afro Diaspora
In the years following the Civil War, many newly freed African Americans began to form
separatist communities or Black Towns as a way to avoid the oppressions of the majority white society.
A main destination for many African Americans was Kansas, in large part aided and encouraged by the
black nationalist and former slave Benjamin "Pap" Singleton. In the 1870s hundreds of black families
settled in Pap's colonies. Singleton founded Nicodemus, Kansas, one of the first and most successful
Black Towns in 1878 and by 1879 it had almost 700 residents. Many of Nicodemus's inhabitants were
Exodusters, nicknamed thus for their participation in the 1879 Kansas Fever Exodus. The town's rapid
growth was sharply curtailed when the town was bypassed by the railroad in 1888 and the residents
slowly relocated to more prosperous towns. This photograph shows an early homestead in Nicodemus,
Kansas. Pap Singleton is third from the left.
In 1888, the freed slaves Isaiah T. Montgomery and Ben Greene founded Mound Bayou,
Mississippi, an experimental planned community for African Americans. Using the teachings of Booker T.
Washington as inspiration, Montgomery and Greene formed the self-governing and economically
independent town that flourished in its initial years. Montgomery, whose Mound Bayou home is shown
here, served as mayor for the town from 1898 to 1902. In addition to a successful political career, he
became close friends with Booker T. Washington, who often used the town as an exemplar of black
independence in his writings. While Mound Bayou has not regained its previous prosperity, the town
continues to be a predominantly black town. In 2000, 98.4 percent of the town's 2,093 people were
black or African American.
As early as the turn of the nineteenth century, many African Americans believed that returning
to Africa was the most viable solution to the bleak social situation in the United States. One of
the wealthiest black people in his time, the sea captain and philanthropist Paul Cuffe encouraged the
return of African Americans to Africa. In 1815, Cuffe along with thirty-eight African Americans sailed to
Sierra Leone in Cuffe's ship, The Traveller. While there had been earlier Back-to-Africa efforts, Cuffe's
was the first one initiated by an African American. While suspicious of their intentions, Cuffe also
worked with the American Colonization Society (ACS), formed in 1817 by a group of white politicians
and clergymen in order to remove free blacks from the United States and return them to Africa. Black
nationalists had much to say about the barely veiled racist motivations of the ACS but Cuffe chose to
work with the group, using their funds in order to help his own cause
In the late nineteenth century Pan-Africanists such as Henry McNeal Turner, Alexander
Crummell, and Edward Wilmot Blyden continued to encourage the emigration of blacks to West Africa.
Henry McNeal Turner was one of the major proponents of the Back-to-Africa movements at that time
and he was especially interested in having Africans Americans return to Africa as Christian missionaries.
Turner encouraged African Americans to relocate to Sierra Leone and Liberia, experimental colonies
formed as destinations for former slaves and free blacks. For Turner, repatriation served several ends.
Not only could Africans Americans spread Christian doctrine and "civilize" Africa but emigration would
also remove them from political and economic difficulties in the United States. In 1876 Turner was
elected honorary vice president of the controversial American Colonization Society.
In the early part of the twentieth century, a new wave of black nationalism swept the country
led by Marcus Garvey, the most significant of all the "classic" black nationalists. In 1914 Garvey founded
the Universal Negro Improvement Association (UNIA) in Jamaica and in 1917 he came to Harlem, New
York, bringing UNIA with him. The organization promoted blackness as a source of pride and beauty
mainly through the promotion of black-owned businesses and a generally separatist ideology. At its
height the UNIA was the largest organization of its kind with 700 branches scattered across the country
and millions of members. Garvey's followers called themselves Garveyites and were known for organizing parades and wearing sharp military-style uniforms in order to show their racial pride. Garvey
himself proved to be quite controversial but his teachings of black independence and pride had a
profound influence on later black nationalists and activists. One of Marcus's Garvey and UNIA's major
endeavors was the Black Star Line, Inc., which greatly helped the UNIA's efforts but was ultimately
Garvey's downfall in the United States.
The Black Star Line was a steamboat enterprise that consisted of three aging, overpriced
steamships that shuttled cargo and passengers to and from Africa. Despite the state of the ships the
Black Star Line garnered a great deal of interest and helped fund many of the UNIA expenses. The
steamship line also served Garvey's repatriation efforts by literally taking African American's back to
Africa. The Black Star Line shut down operations in 1921 due to poor management and in 1923 Garvey
was found guilty of defrauding Black Star Line shareholders and imprisoned. Upon release Garvey was
deported to Jamaica and never returned to the Unites State
Malcolm X, arguably the best-known figure in the history of black separatist movements, is
shown here with Martin Luther King Jr. on 26 March 1964, just a few weeks after Malcolm had broken
ties with the Nation of Islam. Malcolm and King greatly differed in their approaches to achieving a better
life for black people in the United States. X advocated black separatism and self defense from racial
violence inflicted by white people. King adhered to a nonviolent approach to achieving greater racial
equality through racial integration. Malcolm X's highly influential and highly contested book The
Autobiography of Malcolm X (written with Alex Haley) was published in 1965 after his death and served
as a canonical text for these.
Although he did not coin the phrase "Black Power," the civil rights activist and Student Nonviolent Coordinating Committee (SNCC) chairperson Stokely Carmichael is widely credited for popularizing it. "Black Power" became the battle cry for black nationalist groups of the late-1960s and the 1970s. On 16 June 1966, in response to being arrested for trespassing at the March Against Fear, Carmichael proclaimed, "This is the twenty-seventh time I've been arrested, and I ain't going to jail no more. The only way we gonna stop them white men from whupping us is to take over. We been saying freedom for six years and we ain't got nothing. What we gonna start saying now is Black Power!" Black Power soon became a household term as well as an indication of the shifting approaches of how to fight for equal rights. In June 1967, Carmichael was asked to become the prime minister of the burgeoning black nationalist organization, the Black Panther Part
Drawing on the teachings of black nationalists before them, Huey Newton and Bobby Seale formed the Black Panther Party in Oakland, California, in 1966 in response to heightened police brutality. Emerging in a moment of sharpening racial frustration, the Black Panthers brought a new degree of militancy to the ideas of black pride, power, and nationalism, and the group soon became a strong cultural presence in the United States. A socialist revolutionary group, the Panthers advocated for basic needs for black people such as adequate food, shelter, and employment opportunities. They also advocated armed self-defense against white oppressive powers, which earned them a reputation as a dangerous and revolutionary group. This image shows Black Panthers on the stairs of the Seattle federal courthouse in 1969 demanding the release of the Party co-founder Huey P. Newton who had been arrested and charged with the murder of a white police officer. On 16 October 1968 at the Olympic summer games in Mexico City, the track-and-field sprinters Tommie Smith and John Carlos brought Black Power to an international audience. After winning gold and bronze medals, respectively, in the 200-meter sprint, Smith and Carlos took to the podium wearing black socks with no shoes to represent the poverty of black people in the United States and a black scarf to symbolize black pride. During the playing of the national anthem, Smith and Carlos lowered their eyes and each raised a single black-gloved fist in the traditional Black Power salute. Their gesture, meant to protest racism and segregation, was met with a mixed, though largely negative, response. Shamefully, after the ceremony the two Olympians were suspended by the U.S. team
Conclusion
The challenges and struggles that separatist groups face are not purely political, but also often puts them in great physical and even mortal danger, as exemplified in the bombing of the predominantly African American separatist group MOVE. The Philadelphia based group, whose members all took the last name Africa, had a long, tumultuous history with the local police as well as the surrounding communities. On 13 May 1985, the police dropped a bomb on the group's home on Ossage Avenue in West Philadelphia. The police then allowed the fire to burn and it spread rapidly to neighboring buildings and blocks destroying sixty-one homes. Eleven MOVE members died in the fire including five children. Only two members survived the inferno dered to leave Mexico City immediately. Garvey’s project was a bourgeois class project that eschewed revolution and insurgent liberation as a way of resolving underlying social contradictions. His pessimistic view of history (see Watson) leaves many issues unresolved as to the future of Africa in the epoch of modern imperialism. Garvey did not offer any insights into the possibility of a dialectical ontology that opens up the possibility of transcending the modern state in the direction of post national subjectivity. Substantively, “Nationalist modes of political regulation are the form of appearance of the terror that the world market society of capital entails. In short, nationalist displacements of anti-capitalist struggles replicate what they denounce” (Bonefeld 169), reinforcing false inside/outside dichotomies of ‘them’ versus ‘us’ and with the effect of neutralizing “anti-capitalist struggles for the democratic organization of socially necessary labor time by the associated producers themselves” (Bonefeld 169). Historically, nationalist movements have been impervious to the fact that sovereign autonomy is not equitable with self-determination under capitalism. Our human destiny does not rest on racial struggle; rather we must pursue it as part of the quest for our universal humanity.
WORKS CITED
Benn, Denis. The Growth and Development of Political Ideas in the Caribbean, 1774-1983. Kingston:
Institute for Social and Economic Studies, University of the West Indies, Mona, 1987.
Black, Edwin. The War against the Weak: Eugenics and America’s Campaign to Create a Master Race.
New York: Four Walls Eight Windows, 2003.
Blyden, Wilmot. Christianity, Islam and the Negro Race. Edinburgh: Edinburgh UP,1967.
Bonefeld, Werner. “Nationalism and Anti-Semitism in Anti-Globalization Perspective.” Human Dignity:
Social Autonomy and the Critique of Capitalism. Ed. Werner
Bonefeld and Kosmas Psychopedis. Aldershot: Ashgate, 2005. 147-171.
Bonefeld, Werner, and Kosmas Psychopedis, eds. Human Dignity: Social Autonomy and the Critique of
Capitalism. Aldershot: Ashgate, 2005.
Von Clausewitz, Carl. War. Trans. Michael Howard and Peter Paret. London: Everyman’s Library, 1993.
Clarke, Richard L. W. “Roots: a Genealogy of the Barbadian Personality.” The Empowering Impulse:
The Nationalist Tradition in Barbados. Ed. Glenford Howeand Don. D. Marshall. Kingston:
Canoe Press, University of the West Indies,2001. 301-349.
Delaney, Martin Robinson. Principia of Ethnology: the Races and Color with an Archaeological
Compendium of Ethiopian and Egyptian Civilization from Years of Careful Examination and Inquiry. Philadelphia: Harper and Brother, 1895.
Edwards, Bryan. The History (Civil and Commercial) of the British West Indies. 5 Vols. London, 1819.
Froude, James A. The English in the West Indies (or The Bow of Ulysses). London: Longman, Green and
Co., 1888.
Furedi, Frank. The Silent War: Imperialism and the Silent Discourse of Race. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers
UP, 1998.
Garvey, Marcus, Jr. “Garveyism: Some Reflections on its Significance for Today.”
Marcus Garvey and the Vision of Africa. Ed. John Henrik Clarke, with the assistance of Amy Jacques
Garvey. New York: Vintage, 1974. 375-387.
Garvey, Marcus. “The Ideals of Two Races.” Philosophy and Opinions of Marcus Garvey. Vol. 2.
London: Frank Cass, 1967.
Gilroy, Paul. Against Race: Imagining Political Culture beyond the Color Line. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
UP, 2000.
Goldberg, David Theo. The Racial State. Oxford: Blackwell, 2002.
Goody, Jack. The Theft of History. Cambridge: CUP, 2006.
Israel, Jonathan. Enlightenment Contested. Oxford: OUP, 2006.
Jahn, Beate. The Cultural Construction of International Relations. London: PalgraveMacmillan, 2000.
James, C. L. R. A History of the Pan-African Revolt. 2 Ed. Washington, DC: Drum and Spear, 1969.
James, Winston. Holding Aloft the Banner of Ethiopia. London: Verso, 1998.
Kedourie, Ellie. Nationalism. Wiley Blackwell. 1993
Kuhl, Stefan. The Nazi Connection: Eugenics, American Racism and German National Socialism. Oxford:
OUP, 1994.
Lewontin, Richard. “ The Apportionment of Human Diversity.” Evolutionary Biology. Vol. 6. Ed. T.
Dobzhansky, M. K. Hecht, and W. C. Steere. New York: Appleton Century-Cotts, 1972. 396-397.
Long, Edward. English Humanity no Paradox (or an attempt to prove that the English are not a Nation of
Savages). London: T. Lowndes, 1778.
Long, Edward. The History of Jamaica. 3 Vols. London: Lowndes, 1774. Repub. London: Frank Cass,
1970.
Malik, Kenan. The Meaning of Race. New York: New York UP, 1996.
Mills, Charles. The Racial Contract. Ithaca: Cornell UP, 1996.
Montagu, Ashley. Man’s Most Dangerous Myth: the Fallacy of Race. 6 Ed. London: Sge, 1997.
Padmore, George. Pan-Africanism or Communism. Garden City, NY: Double Day, 1971.
Persaud, Randolph B. “Re-envisioning Sovereignty: Marcus Garvey and the Making of a Transnational
Identity." Africa's Challenge to International Relations Theory.
Ed. Kevin C. Dunn and Timothy Shaw. London: Palgrave-Macmillan, 2001. 112-128.
Reid, Julian. “Re-appropriating Clausewitz: the Neglected Dimensions of CounterStrategic Thought.”
Classical Theory in International Relations. Ed. Beate Jahn. Cambridge: CUP, 2006. 277-295.
Rosenberg, Leah R. Nationalism and the Formation of Caribbean Literature. London: Palgrave
Macmillan, 2007.
Thomas, J. J. Froudacity. London, 1889.
van der Pijl, Kees. “Historical Materialism and the Emancipation of Labour.” Historical Materialism and
Globalization. Ed. Mark Rupert and Hazel Smith. London: Routledge, 2002. 129-146.
Watson, Hilbourne A. "Theorizing the Racialization of Global Politics and the Caribbean Experience."
Alternatives 26.4 (2001): 449-483.
Comments
Post a Comment